Yes, one of the limitations that many people see in rationality is that it can't tell us about moral, it can shed light on moral question, namely, that you you can't get from an 'is' to an 'ought' of a this the argument originated with David Hume and became a staple of 20th century analytic philosophy, that it's just a an error, to use, try to use rationality and logic to determine what's what's right or wrong. And there is an element of truth to that, which is Hume absolutely right, that you can't logically prove to me that I should care more about, you know, genocide of 100 million people than a scratch on my pinky, that I haven't made a logical error. When I say, Well, I just - my pinky hurts. And I care about that. And I don't care about those 100 million people. Well, okay. Yeah. And Hume also noted that you can't... if I were to say that I prefer to be healthy and happy and safe and well fed to being miserable, and in pain and lonely, that's not logical, either. There are brute preferences. That... and that reason always is in service of, he put it the passions, but of our wants, and our needs, which are not themselves logical. Okay. On the other hand, once you acknowledge that there are certain things that I want, like, you know, I'd rather not be in pain, I'd rather be well fed call me irrational, but that just the way I'm put together, once I, I am in conversation with you about anything, such as I know that you could make me miserable. And I'd like you not to, I mean, you could, you could step on my foot, you could beat me up, you can hurt my kids. And so my own well being depends on what you do. Well, you start with those, and you kind of get morality pretty quickly. Namely, I can't insist to you that you treat me well, but at the same time, reserve the right to treat you badly. And hopefully, you'll take me seriously. Because there's nothing inherently logical about the difference between me or you. Anything that I insist on for me, I've got to pretty much have to grant to you. That's the basis of the golden rule and the categorical imperative, and the view from nowhere and the veil of ignorance. And so while it is technically true, that you can't get an ought from an is you get to an ought pretty quickly if you combine if you start with self interest and the sociality, that is, there are some things that I want, I can't deny them to you if I want to be in any kind of discourse with you. So that's a theoretical argument. And then I end the book by saying that not not only is that does that show that reason, is not irrelevant to morality, once you grant the premise of self interest and sociality, but in practice, a lot of the great moral movements began with an argument that that you actually had philosophers or activists, thinkers, who laid out an argument for some barbaric practice of the day like, like sadistic torture is a form of criminal punishment, or slavery or persecuting religious heretics are the absolute right of kings. They showed why those practices were not consistent with other values that that people claim to hold. And often the treatises the manifestos would be published in pamphlets that would go viral would get translated into other languages, they'd be debated in pubs and salons and coffee houses. And then they would often then become the law of the land. So I wouldn't say that all moral movements begin with an argument that all arguments can successfully launch moral movements, but an awful lot of them did.